This is a psychology blog which includes items of interest on associated topics in religion and science. The views are those of the author and no one else.
Sunday, 13 November 2011
Last year I published a ghostly picture of an airman at Gosport. Here is another of a woman dressed in 1940's clothes on the balcony of St.Botolph's church. It must be a fake obviously since there are no such things as ghosts...Is it that our mind takes a random pattern of light and shade and creates an image from it which actually isn't there:like the face of Jesus in a piece of toast, or a face in the clouds ?
ST BOTOLPH'S CHURCH
Bishopsgate. London EC2.
In 1982, photographer Chris Brackley took a picture inside this historic old church. The only people present were himself and his wife. When the photograph was developed he was astonished to note that a woman in old-fashioned garb was standing on the balcony to the right of the altar. The negative was subjected to considerable expert analysis, which revealed that that there was no double exposure to the film and it was also proved that none of Chris’s equipment was faulty. The only explanation for the mysterious figure was that someone must have actually been standing on the balcony when the picture was taken. A few years later Chris was contacted by a builder who had been employed on restoration work in St Botolph’s crypt. He explained that, in knocking down a wall he had inadvertently disturbed a pile of old coffins. One had come open to reveal a reasonably well-preserved body the face of which bore an uncanny resemblance to the figure that had made an uninvited appearance in Chris’s photograph.
Saturday, 12 November 2011
Ear Worms and Us!
What triggers an Earworm - the song that's stuck in your head?
![]() |
PYT was triggered by the letters EYC |
Just over 600 participants provided all the information that was needed for a detailed analysis. Predictably, the most frequently cited circumstance was recent exposure to a particular song. "My bloody earworm is that bloody George Harrison song you played yesterday," one 6 Music listener wrote in. "Woke at 4.30 this morning with it going round me head. PLEASE DON'T EVER PLAY IT AGAIN." In relation to this kind of earworm-inducing exposure, the survey revealed the manifold ways that we come into contact with music in modern life, including: music in public places, in gyms, restaurants and shops; radio music; live music; ring tones; another person's humming or singing; and music played in visual media on TV and on the Internet.
However, a song doesn't have to be heard to worm its way inside your head. Many listeners described how earworms had been triggered by association - contact with certain people, rhythms, situations, sounds or words - sometimes with quite obscure links. "On my journey, I read a number plate on a car that ended in the letters 'EYC' which is NOTHING LIKE 'PYT' (by Michael Jackson)," said another listener, "but for some unknown reason, there it was - the song was in my head."
Memories also triggered earworms - for example, driving along the same stretch of road that a song was first heard. And also anticipation. Another listener had "Alive" by Pearl Jam stuck in their head in the days before attending a Pearl Jam concert.
Mood and stress were other triggers. "Prokofiev 'Montagues and Capulets' opening theme. I was writing an email about a distressing subject. I suspect the mood of the piece matched my mood at the time," said an amateur musician. Another listener had Michael Jackson's Man in the Mirror playing in her mind ever since she'd been thinking about the star non-stop and feeling sad (the survey coincided with his death in 2009).
A final theme to emerge from the survey was the way that earworms start playing when we're in a "low attention state", bored or even asleep. "My earworm is 'Mulder and Scully' by Catatonia. In fact I dreamt about running through woods and this was the sound track in my head," said a 6 Music listener. Another survey respondent experienced K'naan "Waving Flag" when mind wandering through a monotonous lab task.
Theoretically, Williamson and her colleagues said earworms can be understood as another manifestation of what Ebbinghaus in the nineteenth century identified as "involuntary memory retrieval". They could even provide a new window through which to study that phenomenon.
"While musical imagery is a skill that many (especially musicians) can utilise to their advantage, involuntary musical imagery (INMI) is an involuntary, spontaneous, cognitive intrusion that, while not necessarily unpleasant or worrying, can prove hard to control," the researchers concluded. "The present study has classified the breadth of circumstances associated with the onset of an INMI episode in everyday life and provided insights into the origins of the pervasive phenomenon, as well as an illustration of how these different contexts might interact."
What about you? What earworms have you experienced lately and what was the context? Please use comments to share your earworm experiences.
_________________________________
Tuesday, 1 November 2011
Why do we like HORROR ?
Why is horror the way it is?
Thursday, 20 October 2011
Are we Blind to Internet Banners ?
Now Guillaume Hervet and his team have attempted to address these points in an eye-tracking study. Thirty-two participants read eight web-pages about choosing a digital camera. On the third, fourth, seventh and eighth pages, a Google-style rectangular text ad (180 x 150 pixels) was embedded in the right-hand side of the editorial content. The second ad was different from the first, and then the same two ads appeared on the seventh and eighth pages, respectively. Also, half the participants were exposed to ads that were congruent with the camera topic of the web-pages; the other half to incongruent ads. All advertised brands were fictitious.
The results may be of some consolation to Google and their advertisers. Eighty-two per cent of the participants did actually look at one or more of the ads. Or put another way: of the 128 ad exposures, 37 per cent were looked at once or more. Had the ad content made a lasting impression? To test this, after the browsing phase, the participants attempted to read the same ads presented in varying degrees of blurry degradation. Their performance was compared to a new group of control participants who hadn't done the earlier web browsing. If performance was superior among the participants who'd earlier been exposed to the ads, this would suggest they had a lasting memory of the ad content. In fact, performance was only superior for web-browsing participants who'd earlier been exposed to ads in a congruent context.
Another aspect to the results is how the participants' behaviour changed over the course of the web browsing. The first and third ads were looked at for longer than the second and fourth ads. This is probably because the second and fourth ads appeared on pages that had been preceded by a page with an ad on it in the same location - the participants seemed to have learned to ignore that area of the page. On the other hand, it seems a couple of pages without ads was enough to restore ad-looking behaviour.
The lessons for web advertisers are clear: don't advertise on every page, vary ad location, and make sure the ad topic is congruent with the web-site content.
Sunday, 18 September 2011
DISGUST: its psychological function....
Total Recoil
- Bodily secretions - faeces (poo), vomit, sweat, spit, blood, pus, sexual fluids
- Body parts - wounds, corpses, toenail clippings
- Decaying food - especially rotting meat and fish, rubbish
- Certain living creatures - flies, maggots, lice, worms, rats, dogs and cats
- People who are ill, contaminated
Excreta is most common cause of disgust around the world. |
The gum of a man's mouth infected with larvae from a sarcophagid fly during a nap in the open. |
People around the world use the same expression to display their disgust. |
Happy New School Year!
Please post comments on the school web site, what are your cures for the blues ?
Saturday, 5 March 2011
Language and thought

Jill Hohenstein's talk last Wednesday demonstrated how psychologists have been attempting to answer a question that is also much-discussed amongst philosophers: what is the relationship between language and thought?
As an experimental psychologist, her work (and the work she cites) involves looking at speakers of interestingly-different languages and seeing whether the differences in language relate to differences in the performance of various non-linguistic tasks.
One example she gave was that of directions. Our language provides us with different ways of thinking about spatial relationships: in absolute terms and in relative terms. In absolute terms, I could say that the main school is South of my current location in Gwyer; in relative terms, I could say that it is straight ahead of me. However, some languages do not provide both of these options: some only allow for the description of absolute spatial relationships.
In order to test whether these differences in languages affected how people thought about spatial relationships, speakers of both languages were given a task where they had to look at an array of objects, then turn around 180 degrees and organise another set of objects “in the same way”. The idea was that the speakers of the “absolute” language should put the objects in the same absolute locations (i.e., if a red circle was at the northern end of the first array they would put a red circle at the northern end of their array), whereas the speakers of languages like English would be able to put the objects either in the same absolute locations or in the same relative locations (i.e., if red circle was on their right of the first array they would put a red circle at the right-hand end of their array).
Professor Hohenstein reported that there had been mixed results from studies such as these, but that there seemed to be some effect of language on response, as predicted. This provided evidence for the view that language does, to some extent, affect the way that we actually think rather than just constraining the ways in which we are able to express our thoughts.
In philosophy, the viewpoint that language structures our thought is known as conceptual relativism, or as the idea that different people could have alternative conceptual schemes. A conceptual scheme is a language, a system of categories that allows us to think and talk about the world and make claims about it. So the claim of conceptual relativism is the claim that there could exist languages that cannot be translated into each other because they carve up the world into such different concepts.
If this were the case, then there would be different “truths” expressable in different languages – true statements could be made in one language that could not be made in another. An interesting paradox is that it is impossible to give an actual example of this relativism of truth claims, because any example of an imaginary untranslatable language would have to be given in our language and thus would not be truly untranslatable. This demonstrates that it is impossible to move outside of our own conceptual scheme and imagine an alternative one.
But not being able to imagine an alternative conceptual scheme does not mean that such a thing is impossible; and we can provide examples which point towards what untranslatable truth claims might look like.
For example, if a group of language speakers had just one word (and one concept) for orange and yellow, then they would be able to say truthfully that “this rose is the same colour as that satsuma”, which cannot be directly translated into English (the indirect, truth-maintaining translation would be something like “this rose is red-or-orange and that satsuma is also red-or-orange”, which is a bit of a mouthful but nevertheless true).
And a small-scale example of real conceptual relativism comes from mathematics: apparently mathematical truths can be expressed in the grammar of Reimannian geometry that cannot be expressed in the grammar of classical, Euclidean geometry.
The studies cited by Professor Hohenstein also point towards the possibility that a radically different language – perhaps one used by creatures with completely different sensory apparatus to us – could cause its users to think about the world in radically different ways to us.
There is some debate in philosophy as to whether the idea of alternative conceptual schemes – languages which cannot be translated into English – makes sense at all, but I think that the insights provided by experimental psychologists suggest that it does, even if such things cannot be imagined.